使婢差奴过一生是什么意思| 马冲什么生肖| 熬夜喝什么汤比较好| 什么是活检| 艾滋病前期有什么症状| 第三产业是什么| 乙肝表面抗原携带者什么意思| 黑色皮肤适合什么颜色的衣服| 草菅人命是什么意思| 存款到100万算什么阶层| 为什么端午节要吃粽子| 火疖子用什么药膏| 王晶为什么不娶邱淑贞| 萌宠是什么意思| xl什么牌子| 孕妇贫血吃什么补血最快| 交媾是什么意思| 晕车药什么时候吃最好| 右眼睛跳是什么原因| 福尔马林是什么| 双鱼座跟什么星座最配| 阑尾炎可以吃什么东西| 束缚的意思是什么| 小儿急性喉炎吃什么药| 百里挑一是什么生肖| 凤凰男什么意思| 鹿晗和邓超什么关系| 泡果酒用什么酒好| 口腔扁平苔藓挂什么科| 什么样的房子风水好| 96166是什么电话| 枪是什么生肖| 益气养阴是什么意思| 酒糟鼻买什么药膏去红| cindy英文名什么意思| 蜘蛛代表什么生肖| 2100年是什么年| 过敏性鼻炎吃什么食物好| 农历10月14日是什么星座| 屋漏偏逢连夜雨是什么意思| 胆囊炎吃什么药好得快| 五月七号是什么星座| 酚妥拉明是什么药| 本来无一物何处惹尘埃是什么意思| 左眼皮跳是什么原因| 胸腔里面像岔气了的疼是什么原因| 高密度脂蛋白胆固醇是什么意思| 什么吃蟑螂| hpv亚临床感染是什么意思| 资金盘是什么意思| 断崖式是什么意思| 鼻子突然出血是什么原因| 梅毒是什么症状图片| 女人吃什么排卵最快| 什么叫释怀| 伟岸一般形容什么人| 什么是抽动症| 甲亢平时要注意什么| 吃人肉会得什么病| 什么是指标生| apple什么意思| 师奶是什么意思| 伴手礼什么意思| 急支糖浆是什么梗| 刚做了人流适合吃什么好| 日语亚麻得是什么意思| 核糖体由什么组成| 吃白糖有什么好处和坏处| 吃什么能补充雌激素| 中指戴戒指代表什么| rag是什么| 波罗蜜多什么意思| 市局副局长什么级别| lov是什么意思| 小孩肺炎吃什么药| 梦见情人是什么意思啊| 移动电源和充电宝有什么区别| 秋天能干什么| 肌肉疼痛吃什么药| 妍字属于五行属什么| 124是什么意思| 湿热是什么意思| 纳入是什么意思| 梨子什么季节成熟| 眼球内容物包括什么| 荆棘是什么意思| 白化病有什么危害吗| 党的执政理念是什么| 400年前是什么朝代| 白细胞多是什么原因| 1996年属什么生肖| 曹操属什么| 人体电解质是什么| 为什么很多人不去庐山| 做梦翻车了什么预兆| 减肥为什么让早上空腹喝咖啡| 两女一杯什么意思| 梦见着大火了是什么征兆| 1898年属什么生肖| 缺钾吃什么食物好| 嘴角生疮是什么原因| 走马观花是什么意思| 10015是什么电话| 甲状腺4b级是什么意思| 蒙氏结节是什么| 蟑螂是什么样子的| 睡不着什么原因| 漂流穿什么衣服| 修女是干什么的| 鱼和什么不能一起吃| 哈乐是什么药| 彰字五行属什么| 右眼皮跳是什么预兆女| 疝气挂什么科| 内分泌失调什么意思| 地球是什么形状的| 朝是什么意思| 做梦梦到和别人吵架是什么意思| 低烧是什么症状和感觉| 艾滋病通过什么途径传播| 横纹肌溶解什么意思| 电风扇什么牌子好| 产生幻觉是什么原因| 断掌是什么意思| 眼睛肿是什么问题| 什么负什么名| 女生什么时候是安全期| 早搏吃什么药最管用| 孕妇梦见鬼是什么预兆| 玉势是什么| 大姨妈来了吃什么对身体好| 微腺瘤是什么| 招风耳是什么意思| 呕吐拉肚子吃什么药| 盆底脱垂有什么症状| 幸灾乐祸什么意思| 羊肠小道什么意思| 慢性鼻窦炎吃什么药| 蝉是什么意思| 动物园里有什么游戏| 曲拉是什么| apc药片是什么药| 一九九七年属什么生肖| 蛇盘疮吃什么药| 什么水果是发物| 经由是什么意思| 中将是什么级别的干部| 过去的日子叫什么日| 脂蛋白高是什么原因| 耳朵外面痒是什么原因| 疏通血管吃什么药最好| 糖尿病筛查做什么检查| 别开生面是什么意思| 吃狗肉有什么危害| 发烧了吃什么食物好| 陆家嘴为什么叫陆家嘴| 什么样的雪莲| 怀孕哭对宝宝有什么影响| 低密度脂蛋白高是什么意思| roa是什么意思| 尿道感染用什么药| 貔貅什么人不能戴| 相刑什么意思| 左附件囊肿注意什么| 肾阳虚有什么症状| 仁字五行属什么| 流清水鼻涕吃什么药| 宫闱是什么意思| 纯棉是什么面料| 早晨起床手肿胀是什么原因| 喉咙干痒是什么原因| 抑郁症看什么科| yellow是什么颜色| 接触隔离什么意思| 什么病治不好| 水满则溢月盈则亏是什么意思| 车辙是什么意思| 吃六味地黄丸有什么好处| 什么的海洋| 眼袋肿是什么原因| 爱而不得是什么感觉| 男人什么时候精子最强| 跑步有什么好处| lll是什么意思| 990金是什么金| 终身为国是什么生肖| 梦见手机坏了是什么意思| 什么食物对心脏有好处| 青光眼是什么症状| 张顺的绰号是什么| 韬略是什么意思| 妇科活检是什么意思| 玉的主要成分是什么| 孕妇咳嗽可以吃什么药| 白凉粉是什么原料做的| 拆线挂什么科| 健脾祛湿吃什么药效果最好| 农历六月初四是什么日子| 参数错误是什么意思| 松垮是什么意思| cin是什么意思| 盆底肌松弛有什么症状| 日生组成什么字| 谨言慎行下一句是什么| 变色龙指什么样的人| 98年是什么命| 雷贝拉唑钠肠溶片什么时候吃| 丙氨酸氨基转移酶高是什么意思| 病毒性结膜炎用什么眼药水| 为什么手臂上有很多很小的点| 水杨酸有什么作用| 水命中什么水命最好| 空腹喝可乐有什么危害| 通勤什么意思| 菠萝蜜什么时候成熟| 半什么三什么| 爱迪生发明什么| 卤牛肉放什么调料| 槟榔为什么那么贵| 什么水果可以减肥| 什么叫服务器| 门静脉增宽是什么意思| 拔腋毛有什么危害| 着凉肚子疼吃什么药| 儿童看包皮挂什么科| 太容易出汗是什么原因| 大小周休息是什么意思| 翻糖蛋糕是什么意思| 眼震电图能查什么病| 牙齿黄用什么牙膏| 洞房是什么意思| 弱精是什么意思| 大姨妈一直不干净是什么原因| 科级干部是什么级别| me是什么基团| 方言是什么意思| 切什么意思| 手掉皮是缺什么维生素| 眼睛干涩发痒用什么药| 7月1日是什么星座| 感冒咳嗽挂什么科| 男人梦到蛇预示着什么| 六月属什么生肖| 夜间胃痛是什么原因| ll是什么意思| 感冒发烧不能吃什么食物| 单反是什么意思| 诺如病毒感染吃什么药| 周杰伦得了什么病| 耳朵痒是什么原因引起的| lh是什么意思| 暖五行属什么| 没事在家可以做些什么| 艾草长什么样子图片| 做狐臭手术挂什么科| ipf是什么病| 为什么会有口腔溃疡| 狗吐黄水吃什么药| 776是什么意思| 家里养泥鳅喂什么东西| 湖南有什么好玩的地方| 白细胞3个加号是什么意思| 月结是什么意思| 自主意识是什么意思| 百度Jump to content

沃尔玛测试货架机器人:秒扫描完一次货架

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 之后,围观游客被聚集在一起,并被劝离现场。

In linguistics and the philosophy of language, pragmatics is the study of how context contributes to meaning. The field of study evaluates how human language is utilized in social interactions, as well as the relationship between the interpreter and the interpreted.[1] Linguists who specialize in pragmatics are called pragmaticians. The field has been represented since 1986 by the International Pragmatics Association (IPrA).

Pragmatics encompasses phenomena including implicature, speech acts, relevance and conversation,[2] as well as nonverbal communication. Theories of pragmatics go hand-in-hand with theories of semantics, which studies aspects of meaning, and syntax, which examines sentence structures, principles, and relationships. Pragmatics, together with semantics and syntactics, is a part of semiotics.[3] The ability to understand another speaker's intended meaning is called pragmatic competence.[4][5][6] In 1938, Charles Morris first distinguished pragmatics as an independent subfield within semiotics, alongside syntax and semantics.[7] Pragmatics emerged as its own subfield in the 1950s after the pioneering work of J. L. Austin and Paul Grice.[8][9]

History

[edit]

The intellectual roots of pragmatics trace back to early 20th-century philosophy and semiotics. The term pragmatics was first introduced by the semiotician Charles Morris in 1938, when he proposed dividing the study of signs (semiology) into three parts: syntax, semantics, and pragmatics.[7] In Morris's formulation, pragmatics would specifically study the relationship between signs and their interpreters (i.e. language users), bringing an external perspective that considers users’ context and responses.[10][11] This idea was influenced by the philosophical tradition of pragmatism (especially the work of C. S. Peirce and colleagues), which emphasized practical consequences and usage in meaning.[12][13] Mid-century logical philosophers like Rudolf Carnap built on Morris's approach by suggesting that pragmatics should explicitly analyze the interaction between language, speakers, and the referents of words, thereby making the study of meaning more context-sensitive.[14] Around the same time, Yehoshua Bar-Hillel (a student of Carnap) argued that certain "indexical" elements of language – words like "I", "here", and "now" whose reference shifts with context – must be a central focus of pragmatics.[15] These early insights laid a foundation for viewing meaning as fundamentally tied to context and use, even before pragmatics was recognized as a distinct linguistic discipline.

In the mid-20th century, a broader "pragmatic turn" took place in the study of language, largely driven by philosophers of language examining how meaning depends on use.[16] The later philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein (esp. Philosophical Investigations, 1953) encapsulated this shift with the dictum that "meaning is use," suggesting that words only gain meaning through their function in language games (concrete social interactions).[17] Around the same period, ordinary language philosophers at Oxford began analyzing language not just as an abstract system but as actions performed in particular contexts.[18][19] A landmark was the work of J. L. Austin, who in the 1950s developed Speech Act Theory.[20] Austin's posthumously published lectures How to Do Things with Words (1962) demonstrated that utterances can perform actions (for example, saying "I apologize" is the act of apologizing) and distinguished different levels of speech acts (the locutionary, illocutionary, and perlocutionary acts).[21][22] His colleague John Searle extended this framework in the late 1960s, elaborating a taxonomy of speech act types and the rules governing acts like asserting, questioning, commanding, etc., thereby firmly establishing speech acts as a core topic in pragmatics.[23][24]

The 1967 book Pragmatics of Human Communication: A Study of Interactional Patterns, Pathologies, and Paradoxes by Paul Watzlawick, Janet Helmick Beavin, and Don D. Jackson, is an early book that featured the word "pragmatics" in its title, but it was used in its own interpretation of Morris's earlier conception of the word. The book is not about linguistics at all, but rather about psychology and family therapy.[25][26] The book relates to Morris's idea of "pragmatics" because it considers, broadly speaking, how communication is affected by context; the focus of the book, however, is rather on how communication is affected by different participants interpreting it differently whose behavior was caused by whose.[27] For instance, one example in the book is that of a husband saying "I withdraw because she nags" and the wife saying "I nag because he withdraws"; a different example is the husband saying he doesn't act because the wife dominates, and the wife saying she takes over because the husband is passive.[28] The book would later influence research on psychotherapy[29] and interpersonal communication,[30][31] as well as the four-sides model, but not linguistics.

A key figure in linguistic pragmatics, H. Paul Grice, advanced the study of pragmatics in the late 1960s and 1970s by explaining how people mean more than they literally say. Grice's theory of conversational implicature (first presented in lectures in 1967, published 1975) proposed that speakers and hearers are guided by a Cooperative Principle and a set of rational conversational maxims (e.g. be truthful, be relevant, be brief, be clear).[32] By adhering to or deliberately flouting these maxims, speakers can imply additional meanings which listeners infer in context. For example, if Alice asks, "Can you pass the salt?" and Bob responds, "There's a salt shaker on the table," Bob's literal statement is simply informative, but pragmatically it implies an answer (affirming that he can pass the salt) without directly saying so. The pioneering contributions of Austin (on speech acts) and Grice (on implicature and conversation) in the 1950s–1970s are often credited with establishing pragmatics as its own subfield within linguistics.[33][16][34] Indeed, before this period, many aspects of meaning that depend on context had been regarded as outside the scope of linguistic theory, but Austin and Grice showed these could be studied systematically.[35]

In the 1970s, pragmatics began to gain broader recognition among linguists as a necessary complement to syntax and semantics;[36] in Boston in 1970, the International Symposium on the Pragmatics of Natural Language was held.[37] As the generative grammar revolution led by Noam Chomsky focused on formal syntax and semantics, it became clear that certain phenomena—such as deixis (context-bound reference words), presuppositions (unstated assumptions underlying utterances), and other context-dependent interpretations—could not be adequately explained by grammar and truth-conditional semantics alone.[38][39] Pragmatics emerged to address this "leftover" territory: those aspects of meaning and understanding that require speaker intentions, listener inferences, and real-world knowledge.[40] During this time, two different scholarly traditions in pragmatics crystallized. The first was the Anglo-American tradition, rooted in analytic philosophy of language and exemplified by the work of Austin, Searle, Grice, and their followers.[41] The second was a European continental approach (sometimes called the perspective or functional view of pragmatics), which treated pragmatics as a more holistic perspective on all language behavior, influenced by fields like sociology and anthropology.[42] Despite differing emphases – the Anglo-American school often analyzing micro-level utterances and logical inference, and the Continental school viewing pragmatics as a general functional dimension of language – both contributed to the growth of the field in the 1970s and 1980s.[36][43] By the early 1980s, the institutional and scholarly maturity of pragmatics was evident: a dedicated Journal of Pragmatics was founded in 1977, comprehensive textbooks and monographs on pragmatics (by authors such as Stephen Levinson and Geoffrey Leech) appeared in 1983, and an International Pragmatics Association (IPrA) was established in 1987 to coordinate research in the field.[44][45] These milestones marked pragmatics' definitive emergence as an independent discipline within linguistics, concerned specifically with language use and contextual meaning.[46]

Areas of interest

[edit]
  • The study of the speaker's meaning focusing not on the phonetic or grammatical form of an utterance but on what the speaker's intentions and beliefs are.
  • The study of the meaning in context and the influence that a given context can have on the message. It requires knowledge of the speaker's identities, and the place and time of the utterance.
  • The study of implicatures: the things that are communicated even though they are not explicitly expressed.[47]
  • The study of relative distance, both social and physical, between speakers in order to understand what determines the choice of what is said and what is not said.[48]
  • The study of what is not meant, as opposed to the intended meaning: what is unsaid and unintended, or unintentional.[49]
  • Information structure, the study of how utterances are marked in order to efficiently manage the common ground of referred entities between speaker and hearer.[50]
  • Formal Pragmatics, the study of those aspects of meaning and use for which context of use is an important factor by using the methods and goals of formal semantics.
  • The study of the role of pragmatics in the development of children with autism spectrum disorders or developmental language disorder (DLD).[51]

Ambiguity

[edit]

Ambiguity refers to when it is difficult to infer meaning without knowing the context, the identity of the speaker or the speaker's intent. For example, the sentence "You have a green light" is ambiguous, as without knowing the context, one could reasonably interpret it as meaning:

  • the space that belongs to you has green ambient lighting;
  • you are driving through a green traffic signal;
  • you no longer have to wait to continue driving;
  • you are permitted to proceed in a non-driving context;
  • your body is cast in a greenish glow;
  • you possess a light source which radiates green; or
  • you possess a light with a green surface.

Another example of an ambiguous sentence is, "I went to the bank." This is an example of lexical ambiguity, as the word bank can either be in reference to a place where money is kept, or the edge of a river. To understand what the speaker is truly saying, it is a matter of context, which is why it is pragmatically ambiguous as well.[52]

Similarly, the sentence "Sherlock saw the man with binoculars" could mean that Sherlock observed the man by using binoculars, or it could mean that Sherlock observed a man who was holding binoculars (syntactic ambiguity).[53] The meaning of the sentence depends on an understanding of the context and the speaker's intent. As defined in linguistics, a sentence is an abstract entity: a string of words divorced from non-linguistic context, as opposed to an utterance, which is a concrete example of a speech act in a specific context. The more closely conscious subjects stick to common words, idioms, phrasings, and topics, the more easily others can surmise their meaning; the further they stray from common expressions and topics, the wider the variations in interpretations. That suggests that sentences do not have intrinsic meaning, that there is no meaning associated with a sentence or word, and that either can represent an idea only symbolically. The cat sat on the mat is a sentence in English. If someone were to say to someone else, "The cat sat on the mat", the act is itself an utterance. That implies that a sentence, term, expression or word cannot symbolically represent a single true meaning; such meaning is underspecified (which cat sat on which mat?) and potentially ambiguous. By contrast, the meaning of an utterance can be inferred through knowledge of both its linguistic and non-linguistic contexts (which may or may not be sufficient to resolve ambiguity). In mathematics, with Berry's paradox, there arises a similar systematic ambiguity with the word "definable".

Referential uses of language

[edit]

The referential uses of language are how signs are used to refer to certain items. A sign is the link or relationship between a signified and the signifier as defined by de Saussure and Jean-René Huguenin. The signified is some entity or concept in the world. The signifier represents the signified. An example would be:

Signified: the concept cat
Signifier: the word "cat"

The relationship between the two gives the sign meaning. The relationship can be explained further by considering what is meant by "meaning." In pragmatics, there are two different types of meaning to consider: semantic-referential meaning and indexical meaning.[54] Semantic-referential meaning refers to the aspect of meaning, which describes events in the world that are independent of the circumstance they are uttered in. An example would be propositions such as:

"Santa Claus eats cookies."

In this case, the proposition is describing that Santa Claus eats cookies. The meaning of the proposition does not rely on whether or not Santa Claus is eating cookies at the time of its utterance. Santa Claus could be eating cookies at any time and the meaning of the proposition would remain the same. The meaning is simply describing something that is the case in the world. In contrast, the proposition, "Santa Claus is eating a cookie right now", describes events that are happening at the time the proposition is uttered.

Semantic-referential meaning is also present in meta-semantical statements such as:

Tiger: carnivorous, a mammal

If someone were to say that a tiger is a carnivorous animal in one context and a mammal in another, the definition of tiger would still be the same. The meaning of the sign tiger is describing some animal in the world, which does not change in either circumstance.

Indexical meaning, on the other hand, is dependent on the context of the utterance and has rules of use. By rules of use, it is meant that indexicals can tell when they are used, but not what they actually mean.

Example: "I"

Whom "I" refers to, depends on the context and the person uttering it.

As mentioned, these meanings are brought about through the relationship between the signified and the signifier. One way to define the relationship is by placing signs in two categories: referential indexical signs, also called "shifters", and pure indexical signs.

Referential indexical signs are signs where the meaning shifts depending on the context hence the nickname "shifters." 'I' would be considered a referential indexical sign. The referential aspect of its meaning would be '1st person singular' while the indexical aspect would be the person who is speaking (refer above for definitions of semantic-referential and indexical meaning). Another example would be:

"This"
Referential: singular count
Indexical: Close by

A pure indexical sign does not contribute to the meaning of the propositions at all. It is an example of a "non-referential use of language."

A second way to define the signified and signifier relationship is C.S. Peirce's Peircean Trichotomy. The components of the trichotomy are the following:

1. Icon: the signified resembles the signifier (signified: a dog's barking noise, signifier: bow-wow)[55]
2. Index: the signified and signifier are linked by proximity or the signifier has meaning only because it is pointing to the signified[55]
3. Symbol: the signified and signifier are arbitrarily linked (signified: a cat, signifier: the word cat)[55]

These relationships allow signs to be used to convey intended meaning. If two people were in a room and one of them wanted to refer to a characteristic of a chair in the room he would say "this chair has four legs" instead of "a chair has four legs." The former relies on context (indexical and referential meaning) by referring to a chair specifically in the room at that moment while the latter is independent of the context (semantico-referential meaning), meaning the concept chair.[55]

Referential expressions in conversation

[edit]

Referring to things and people is a common feature of conversation, and conversants do so collaboratively. Individuals engaging in discourse utilize pragmatics.[56] In addition, individuals within the scope of discourse cannot help but avoid intuitive use of certain utterances or word choices in an effort to create communicative success.[56] The study of referential language is heavily focused upon definite descriptions and referent accessibility. Theories have been presented for why direct referent descriptions occur in discourse.[57] (In layman's terms: why reiteration of certain names, places, or individuals involved or as a topic of the conversation at hand are repeated more than one would think necessary.) Four factors are widely accepted for the use of referent language including (i) competition with a possible referent, (ii) salience of the referent in the context of discussion (iii) an effort for unity of the parties involved, and finally, (iv) a blatant presence of distance from the last referent.[56]

Referential expressions are a form of anaphora.[57] They are also a means of connecting past and present thoughts together to create context for information at hand. Analyzing the context of a sentence and determining whether or not the use of referent expression is necessary is highly reliant upon the author/speaker's digression- and is correlated strongly with the use of pragmatic competency.[57][56]

Nonreferential uses of language

[edit]

Silverstein's "Pure" Indexes

[edit]

Michael Silverstein has argued that "nonreferential" or "pure" indices do not contribute to an utterance's referential meaning but instead "signal some particular value of one or more contextual variables."[58] Although nonreferential indexes are devoid of semantico-referential meaning, they do encode "pragmatic" meaning.

The sorts of contexts that such indexes can mark are varied. Examples include:

  • Sex indexes are affixes or inflections that index the sex of the speaker, e.g. the verb forms of female Koasati speakers take the suffix "-s".
  • Deference indexes are words that signal social differences (usually related to status or age) between the speaker and the addressee. The most common example of a deference index is the V form in a language with a T–V distinction, the widespread phenomenon in which there are multiple second-person pronouns that correspond to the addressee's relative status or familiarity to the speaker. Honorifics are another common form of deference index and demonstrate the speaker's respect or esteem for the addressee via special forms of address and/or self-humbling first-person pronouns.
  • An Affinal taboo index is an example of avoidance speech that produces and reinforces sociological distance, as seen in the Aboriginal Dyirbal language of Australia. In that language and some others, there is a social taboo against the use of the everyday lexicon in the presence of certain relatives (mother-in-law, child-in-law, paternal aunt's child, and maternal uncle's child). If any of those relatives are present, a Dyirbal speaker has to switch to a completely separate lexicon reserved for that purpose.

In all of these cases, the semantico-referential meaning of the utterances is unchanged from that of the other possible (but often impermissible) forms, but the pragmatic meaning is vastly different.

The performative

[edit]

J. L. Austin introduced the concept of the performative, contrasted in his writing with "constative" (i.e. descriptive) utterances. According to Austin's original formulation, a performative is a type of utterance characterized by two distinctive features:

  • It is not truth-evaluable (i.e. it is neither true nor false)
  • Its uttering performs an action rather than simply describing one

Examples:

  • "I hereby pronounce you man and wife."
  • "I accept your apology."
  • "This meeting is now adjourned."

To be performative, an utterance must conform to various conditions involving what Austin calls felicity. These deal with things like appropriate context and the speaker's authority. For instance, when a couple has been arguing and the husband says to his wife that he accepts her apology even though she has offered nothing approaching an apology, his assertion is infelicitous: because she has made neither expression of regret nor request for forgiveness, there exists none to accept, and thus no act of accepting can possibly happen.

Formalization

[edit]

There has been a great amount of discussion on the boundary between semantics and pragmatics[59] and there are many different formalizations of aspects of pragmatics linked to context dependence. Particularly interesting cases are the discussions on the semantics of indexicals and the problem of referential descriptions, a topic developed after the theories of Keith Donnellan.[60] A proper logical theory of formal pragmatics has been developed by Carlo Dalla Pozza, according to which it is possible to connect classical semantics (treating propositional contents as true or false) and intuitionistic semantics (dealing with illocutionary forces). The presentation of a formal treatment of pragmatics appears to be a development of the Fregean idea of assertion sign as formal sign of the act of assertion.

Rational Speech Act and Probabilistic Pragmatics

[edit]

Over the past decade, many probabilistic and Bayesian methods have become very popular in the modelling of pragmatics, of which the most successful framework has been the Rational Speech Act[61] framework developed by Noah Goodman and Michael C. Frank, which has already seen much use in the analysis of metaphor,[62] hyperbole[63] and politeness.[64] In the Rational Speech Act, listeners and speakers both reason about the other's reasoning concerning the literal meaning of the utterances, and as such, the resulting interpretation depends, but is not necessarily determined by the literal truth conditional meaning of an utterance, and so it uses recursive reasoning to pursue a broadly Gricean co-operative ideal.

In the most basic form of the Rational Speech Act, there are three levels of inference; Beginning from the highest level, the pragmatic listener will reason about the pragmatic speaker , and will then infer the likely world state taking into account that has deliberately chosen to produce utterance , while chooses to produce utterance by reasoning about how the literal listener will understand the literal meaning of and so will attempt to maximise the chances that will correctly infer the world state . As such, a simple schema of the Rational Speech Act reasoning hierarchy can be formulated for use in a reference game such that:[65]

[edit]

There is considerable overlap between pragmatics and sociolinguistics, since both share an interest in linguistic meaning as determined by usage in a speech community. However, sociolinguists tend to be more interested in variations in language within such communities. Influences of philosophy and politics are also present in the field of pragmatics, as the dynamics of societies and oppression are expressed through language[66]

Pragmatics helps anthropologists relate elements of language to broader social phenomena; it thus pervades the field of linguistic anthropology. Because pragmatics describes generally the forces in play for a given utterance, it includes the study of power, gender, race, identity, and their interactions with individual speech acts. For example, the study of code switching directly relates to pragmatics, since a switch in code effects a shift in pragmatic force.[67]

According to Charles W. Morris, pragmatics tries to understand the relationship between signs and their users, while semantics tends to focus on the actual objects or ideas to which a word refers, and syntax (or "syntactics") examines relationships among signs or symbols. Semantics is the literal meaning of an idea whereas pragmatics is the implied meaning of the given idea.

Speech Act Theory, pioneered by J. L. Austin and further developed by John Searle, centers around the idea of the performative, a type of utterance that performs the very action it describes. Speech Act Theory's examination of Illocutionary Acts has many of the same goals as pragmatics, as outlined above.

Computational Pragmatics, as defined by Victoria Fromkin, concerns how humans can communicate their intentions to computers with as little ambiguity as possible.[68] That process, integral to the science of natural language processing (seen as a sub-discipline of artificial intelligence), involves providing a computer system with some database of knowledge related to a topic and a series of algorithms, which control how the system responds to incoming data, using contextual knowledge to more accurately approximate natural human language and information processing abilities. Reference resolution, how a computer determines when two objects are different or not, is one of the most important tasks of computational pragmatics.

In literary theory

[edit]

Pragmatics (more specifically, Speech Act Theory's notion of the performative) underpins Judith Butler's theory of gender performativity. In Gender Trouble, they claim that gender and sex are not natural categories, but socially constructed roles produced by "reiterative acting."

In Excitable Speech they extend their theory of performativity to hate speech and censorship, arguing that censorship necessarily strengthens any discourse it tries to suppress and therefore, since the state has sole power to define hate speech legally, it is the state that makes hate speech performative.

Jacques Derrida remarked that some work done under Pragmatics aligned well with the program he outlined in his book Of Grammatology.

émile Benveniste argued that the pronouns "I" and "you" are fundamentally distinct from other pronouns because of their role in creating the subject.

Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari discuss linguistic pragmatics in the fourth chapter of A Thousand Plateaus ("November 20, 1923--Postulates of Linguistics"). They draw three conclusions from Austin: (1) A performative utterance does not communicate information about an act second-hand, but it is the act; (2) Every aspect of language ("semantics, syntactics, or even phonematics") functionally interacts with pragmatics; (3) There is no distinction between language and speech. This last conclusion attempts to refute Saussure's division between langue and parole and Chomsky's distinction between deep structure and surface structure simultaneously.[69]

Significant works and concepts

[edit]

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Mey, Jacob L. (2006). "Pragmatics: Overview". In Brown, E. K.; Anderson, Anne (eds.). Encyclopedia of language & linguistics (2nd ed.). Amsterdam: Elsevier. pp. 51–62. doi:10.1016/B0-08-044854-2/00306-0. ISBN 978-0-08-044854-1.
  2. ^ Mey, Jacob L. (1993) Pragmatics: An Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell (2nd ed. 2001).
  3. ^ Posner, Roland 1997. Pragmatics. In Roland Posner, Klaus Robering & Thomas A. Sebeok (eds.), Semiotics: A Handbook on the Sign-Theoretic Foundations of Nature and Culture, vol. 1, 219–246. Berlin: De Gruyter.
  4. ^ Kim, Daejin; Hall, Joan Kelly (2002). "The Role of an Interactive Book Reading Program in the Development of Second Language Pragmatic Competence". The Modern Language Journal. 86 (3): 332–348. doi:10.1111/1540-4781.00153. JSTOR 1192847.
  5. ^ Takimoto, Masahiro (2008). "The Effects of Deductive and Inductive Instruction on the Development of Language Learners' Pragmatic Competence". The Modern Language Journal. 92 (3): 369–386. doi:10.1111/j.1540-4781.2008.00752.x. JSTOR 25173064.
  6. ^ Koike, Dale April (1989). "Pragmatic Competence and Adult L2 Acquisition: Speech Acts in Interlanguage". The Modern Language Journal. 73 (3): 279–289. doi:10.1111/j.1540-4781.1989.tb06364.x. JSTOR 327002.
  7. ^ a b Israel, Michael (2011). The grammar of polarity: Pragmatics, sensitivity, and the logic of scales. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 10.
  8. ^ Kroeger, Paul R. (2025-08-06). Analyzing meaning: An introduction to semantics and pragmatics (2nd ed.). Berlin: Language Science Press. pp. 12, 141. doi:10.5281/ZENODO.2538330. ISBN 978-3-96110-136-8.
  9. ^ Coppock, Elizabeth; Champollion, Lucas (2019). Invitation to formal semantics (PDF) (2019 ed.). p. 37. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2025-08-06. Retrieved 2025-08-06.[verification needed]
  10. ^ Niu, Min; Dechsubha, Thawascha. "The Development of Pragmatics in Morris's Behavioral Semiotics: Semiotic Perspective". osf.io. doi:10.31219/osf.io/6w73v. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  11. ^ Grzybek, Peter (2025-08-06), "4 Semiotic and Semantic Aspects of the Proverb", Introduction to Paremiology, De Gruyter Open Poland, pp. 68–111, doi:10.2478/9783110410167.4, ISBN 978-3-11-041016-7, retrieved 2025-08-06
  12. ^ Bogdanovic, Milos (2020). "Philosophical implications of Morris' semiotic theory". Filozofija I Drustvo. 31 (1): 108–125. doi:10.2298/FID2001108B. ISSN 0353-5738.
  13. ^ Wagner, Anne; Matulewska, Aleksandra (2025-08-06). Research Handbook on Jurilinguistics. Edward Elgar Publishing. p. 71. ISBN 978-1-80220-724-8.
  14. ^ Uebel, Thomas (June 2013). "Pragmatics in Carnap and Morris and the Bipartite Metatheory Conception". Erkenntnis. 78 (3): 523–546. doi:10.1007/s10670-011-9352-5. ISSN 0165-0106.
  15. ^ Szabó, Zoltán Gendler (2025-08-06), Lepore, Ernie; Smith, Barry C. (eds.), "The Distinction between Semantics and Pragmatics", The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, Oxford University Press, pp. 361–390, doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199552238.003.0017, ISBN 978-0-19-955223-8, retrieved 2025-08-06
  16. ^ a b Niu, Min (2025-08-06). "The origin and development of pragmatics as a study of meaning: semiotic perspective". Language and Semiotic Studies. 9 (1): 54–78. doi:10.1515/lass-2023-0002. ISSN 2751-7160.
  17. ^ Biletzki, Anat; Matar, Anat (2023), "Ludwig Wittgenstein", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2023 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2025-08-06
  18. ^ Godart-Wendling, Béatrice (2025-08-06), "History of Analytic Philosophy of Language", Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics, doi:10.1093/acrefore/9780199384655.013.446, ISBN 978-0-19-938465-5, retrieved 2025-08-06
  19. ^ "Ordinary Language Philosophy | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  20. ^ Longworth, Guy (2023), "John Langshaw Austin", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2023 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2025-08-06
  21. ^ Kissine, Mikhail (2008). "Locutionary, Illocutionary, Perlocutionary". Language and Linguistics Compass. 2 (6): 1189–1202. doi:10.1111/j.1749-818X.2008.00093.x. ISSN 1749-818X.
  22. ^ Searle, John R. (1968). "Austin on Locutionary and Illocutionary Acts". The Philosophical Review. 77 (4): 405–424. doi:10.2307/2183008. ISSN 0031-8108. JSTOR 2183008.
  23. ^ Cohen, L. Jonathan (1970). "Searle's Theory of Speech Acts". The Philosophical Review. 79 (4): 545–557. doi:10.2307/2184294. ISSN 0031-8108. JSTOR 2184294.
  24. ^ Green, Mitchell (2021), "Speech Acts", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2025-08-06
  25. ^ Allman, Lawrence R. (1982). "The Aesthetic Preference: Overcoming the Pragmatic Error". Family Process. 21 (1): 43–56. doi:10.1111/j.1545-5300.1982.00043.x. ISSN 1545-5300. PMID 7067796.
  26. ^ Codoban, Aurel (2025-08-06), Micle, Maria; Clitan, Gheorghe (eds.), "The Communication Background of Philosophical Counseling" (PDF), Innovative Instruments for Community Development in Communication and Education, Trivent Publishing, pp. 265–276, doi:10.22618/tp.pcms.20216.360019, ISBN 978-615-81689-4-6, retrieved 2025-08-06
  27. ^ Berger, Charles R; Roloff, Michael E; Wilson, Steve R; Dillard, James Price; Caughlin, John; Solomon, Denise, eds. (2025-08-06). The International Encyclopedia of Interpersonal Communication (1 ed.). Wiley. doi:10.1002/9781118540190.wbeic188. ISBN 978-1-118-30605-5.
  28. ^ Watzlawick, Paul; Bavelas, Janet Beavin; Jackson, Don D. (2014). Pragmatics of human communication: a study of interactional patterns, pathologies, and paradoxes (First published as a Norton paperback 2011, reissued 2014 ed.). New York London: W. W. Norton & Company, Inc. pp. 56–58, 110–117. ISBN 978-0-393-71059-5.
  29. ^ Rohrbaugh, Michael J.; Shoham, Varda (2001). "Brief Therapy Based on Interrupting Ironic Processes: The Palo Alto Model". Clinical Psychology. 8 (1): 66–81. doi:10.1093/clipsy.8.1.66. ISSN 0969-5893. PMC 2789564. PMID 19997533.
  30. ^ Fialkoff, Yonatan; Pinchevski, Amit (2023). "From System to Skill: Palo Alto Group's Contested Legacy of Communication". International Journal of Communication. 17 (19): 541–559.
  31. ^ Demetriades, Stefanie Z; Walter, Nathan; Holbert, R Lance (2025-08-06). "Ushering in an age of scientific principles for communication research". Human Communication Research. 50 (2): 276–284. doi:10.1093/hcr/hqad038. ISSN 1468-2958.
  32. ^ Davis, Wayne (2024), "Implicature", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2025-08-06
  33. ^ Hudson, Mutsuko Endo; Matsumoto, Yoshiko; Mori, Junko (2025-08-06). Pragmatics of Japanese: Perspectives on grammar, interaction and culture. John Benjamins Publishing Company. p. 2. ISBN 978-90-272-6440-4.
  34. ^ Bojic, Ljubisa; Kovacevic, Predrag; Cabarkapa, Milan (2025-08-06). "GPT-4 Surpassing Human Performance in Linguistic Pragmatics". arXiv:2312.09545v1 [cs.CL].
  35. ^ Solan, Lawrence; Ainsworth, Janet; Shuy, Roger W. (2025-08-06). Speaking of Language and Law: Conversations on the Work of Peter Tiersma. Oxford University Press. p. 252. ISBN 978-0-19-933419-3.
  36. ^ a b Jucker, Andreas H. (2012), Jaszczolt, Kasia M.; Allan, Keith (eds.), "Pragmatics in the history of linguistic thought", The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, Cambridge Handbooks in Language and Linguistics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 495–512, doi:10.1017/cbo9781139022453.027, ISBN 978-0-521-19207-1, retrieved 2025-08-06
  37. ^ Li, Minghui; Sun, Jianguang (2023). "The Current State of Research and Analysis of Pragmatics". European Journal of English Language and Literature Studies. 11 (2): 1–9. doi:10.37745/ejells.2013/vol11n319. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  38. ^ Morgan, Jerry L. (1977). "Linguistics: The Relation of Pragmatics to Semantics and Syntax". Annual Review of Anthropology. 6: 57–67. doi:10.1146/annurev.an.06.100177.000421. ISSN 0084-6570. JSTOR 2949325.
  39. ^ Taavitsainen, Irma; Jucker, Andreas H. (2025-08-06), "1. Trends and developments in historical pragmatics", Historical Pragmatics, De Gruyter Mouton, pp. 3–32, doi:10.1515/9783110214284.1.3, ISBN 978-3-11-021428-4, retrieved 2025-08-06
  40. ^ Korta, Kepa; Perry, John (2024), "Pragmatics", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2025-08-06
  41. ^ Anchimbe, Eric A. (2025-08-06). Offers and Offer Refusals: A postcolonial pragmatics perspective on World Englishes. John Benjamins Publishing Company. p. 31. ISBN 978-90-272-6328-5.
  42. ^ Verschueren, Jef (2025-08-06), Huang, Yan (ed.), "Continental European Perspective View", The Oxford Handbook of Pragmatics, Oxford University Press, pp. 120–131, doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199697960.013.9, ISBN 978-0-19-969796-0, retrieved 2025-08-06
  43. ^ Jucker, Andreas H. (2025-08-06), Brinton, Laurel; Bergs, Alexander (eds.), "Chapter 9: Pragmatics and Discourse", Historical Outlines from Sound to Text, De Gruyter, pp. 165–184, doi:10.1515/9783110525281-009, ISBN 978-3-11-052528-1, retrieved 2025-08-06
  44. ^ Bublitz, Wolfram (2011). Foundations of Pragmatics. Handbooks of Pragmatics [HOPS] Ser. Neal R. Norrick. Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter, Inc. p. 158. ISBN 978-3-11-021426-0.
  45. ^ Meeuwis, Michael; ?stman, Jan-Ola (2012). Pragmaticizing Understanding: Studies for Jef Verschueren. John Benjamins Publishing. p. 2. ISBN 978-90-272-1191-0.
  46. ^ Taavitsainen, Irma; Jucker, Andreas H.; Tuominen, Jukka (2025-08-06). Diachronic Corpus Pragmatics. John Benjamins Publishing Company. p. 7. ISBN 978-90-272-7071-9.
  47. ^ "What is Pragmatics? - Definition & Examples - Video & Lesson Transcript". study.com. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  48. ^ "Definition of PRAGMATICS". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  49. ^ Leigh, Karen (2025-08-06). "What are Pragmatic Language Skills?". Sensational Kids. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  50. ^ Zimmermann, Malte (2016). "Information Structure". Linguistics. doi:10.1093/OBO/9780199772810-0130. ISBN 978-0-19-977281-0.
  51. ^ Andrés-Roqueta, Clara; Katsos, Napoleon (2020). "A Distinction Between Linguistic and Social Pragmatics Helps the Precise Characterization of Pragmatic Challenges in Children with Autism Spectrum Disorders and Developmental Language Disorder" (PDF). Journal of Speech, Language, and Hearing Research. 63 (5): 1494–1508. doi:10.1044/2020_JSLHR-19-00263. hdl:10234/190618. PMID 32379523. S2CID 218554970.
  52. ^ "What is pragmatics? – All About Linguistics". Archived from the original on 2025-08-06. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  53. ^ von Fintel, Kai (2004). "24.903 / 24.933 Language and its Structure III: Semantics and Pragmatics". MIT OpenCourseWare. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Archived from the original on April 9, 2010. Retrieved October 17, 2017.
  54. ^ Treanor, Fergal, Pragmatics and Indexicality - A very short overview
  55. ^ a b c d Port, Robert F. (September 4, 2000). "Icon, Index and Symbol: Types of Signs". cs.indiana.edu. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  56. ^ a b c d Almor, Amit; Nair, Veena A. (2007). "The Form of Referential Expressions in Discourse" (PDF). Language and Linguistics Compass. 1 (1–2): 84–99. doi:10.1111/j.1749-818X.2007.00009.x. ISSN 1749-818X. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2025-08-06.
  57. ^ a b c Vonk, Wietske; Hustinx, Lettica G. M. M.; Simons, Wim H. G. (1992). "The use of referential expressions in structuring discourse". Language and Cognitive Processes. 7 (3): 301–333. doi:10.1080/01690969208409389. hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-000E-E736-D. ISSN 0169-0965.
  58. ^ Silverstein 1976.
  59. ^ "see for instance F.Domaneschi. C. Penco, What is Said and What is Not, CSLI Publication, Stanford".
  60. ^ see for instance S. Neale, Descriptions, 1990
  61. ^ Goodman, Noah D.; Frank, Michael C. (November 2016). "Pragmatic Language Interpretation as Probabilistic Inference". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 20 (11): 818–829. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2016.08.005. ISSN 1364-6613. PMID 27692852.
  62. ^ Kao, Justine T.; Bergen, Leon; Goodman, Noah D. (2014). "Formalizing the Pragmatics of Metaphor Understanding". Cognitive Science. S2CID 13623227.
  63. ^ Kao, Justine T.; Wu, Jean Y.; Bergen, Leon; Goodman, Noah D. (2025-08-06). "Nonliteral understanding of number words". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 111 (33): 12002–12007. Bibcode:2014PNAS..11112002K. doi:10.1073/pnas.1407479111. hdl:1721.1/95752. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 4143012. PMID 25092304.
  64. ^ Yoon, Erica J.; Frank, Michael C.; Tessler, Michael Henry; Goodman, Noah D. (2025-08-06). Polite speech emerges from competing social goals (Report). doi:10.31234/osf.io/67ne8.
  65. ^ Scontras, Gregory; Tessler, Michael Henry; Franke, Michael. "Introducing the Rational Speech Act framework". Probabilistic language understanding: An introduction to the Rational Speech Act framework. Archived from the original on October 1, 2023. Retrieved 17 February 2024.
  66. ^ Rajagopalan, K. (2006). "Social Aspects of Pragmatics". Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics. pp. 434–440. doi:10.1016/B0-08-044854-2/00316-3. ISBN 9780080448541.
  67. ^ Duranti 1997.
  68. ^ Fromkin, Victoria (2014). Introduction to Language. Boston, Ma.: Wadsworth, Cengage Learning. p. 508. ISBN 978-1133310686.
  69. ^ Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari (1987) [1980]. A Thousand Plateaus. University of Minnesota Press.

References

[edit]
  • Austin, J. L. (1962) How to Do Things With Words. Oxford University Press.
  • Ariel, Mira (2008), Pragmatics and Grammar, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Ariel, Mira (2010). Defining Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-73203-1.
  • Brown, Penelope, and Stephen C. Levinson. (1978) Politeness: Some Universals in Language Usage. Cambridge University Press.
  • Carston, Robyn (2002) Thoughts and Utterances: The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication. Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Clark, Herbert H. (1996) "Using Language". Cambridge University Press.
  • Cole, Peter, ed.. (1978) Pragmatics. (Syntax and Semantics, 9). New York: Academic Press.
  • Dijk, Teun A. van. (1977) Text and Context. Explorations in the Semantics and Pragmatics of Discourse. London: Longman.
  • Grice, H. Paul. (1989) Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.
  • Laurence R. Horn and Gregory Ward. (2005) The Handbook of Pragmatics. Blackwell.
  • Leech, Geoffrey N. (1983) Principles of Pragmatics. London: Longman.
  • Levinson, Stephen C. (1983) Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press.
  • Levinson, Stephen C. (2000). Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. MIT Press.
  • Lin, G. H. C.; Perkins, L. (2005). "Cross-cultural discourse of giving and accepting gifts" (PDF). International Journal of Communication. 16 (1): 103–112.
  • Moumni, Hassan (2005). Politeness in Parliamentary Discourse : A Comparative Pragmatic Study of British and Moroccan MPs’ Speech Acts at Question Time. Unpub. Ph.D. Thesis. Mohammed V University, Rabat, Morocco.
  • Mey, Jacob L. (1993) Pragmatics: An Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell (2nd ed. 2001).
  • Korta, Kepa; Perry, John (2006). "Pragmatics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Potts, Christopher. (2005) The Logic of Conventional Implicatures. Oxford Studies in Theoretical Linguistics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Robinson, Douglas. (2003). Performative Linguistics: Speaking and Translating as Doing Things With Words. London and New York: Routledge.
  • Robinson, Douglas. (2006). Introducing Performative Pragmatics. London and New York: Routledge.
  • Sperber, Dan; Wilson, Deirdre (2005). "Pragmatics". In Jackson, F.; Smith, M. (eds.). Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 468–501. Archived from the original on 2025-08-06. Also available from ucl.ac.uk.
  • Thomas, Jenny (1995) Meaning in Interaction: An Introduction to Pragmatics. Longman.
  • Verschueren, Jef (1999). Understanding Pragmatics (PDF). London: Edward Arnold. ISBN 978-0-340-64623-6. Retrieved 1 May 2024. Also available from the Internet Archive.
  • Verschueren, Jef, Jan-Ola ?stman, Jan Blommaert, eds. (1995) Handbook of Pragmatics. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
  • Watzlawick, Paul, Janet Helmick Beavin and Don D. Jackson (1967) Pragmatics of Human Communication: A Study of Interactional Patterns, Pathologies, and Paradoxes. New York: Norton.
  • Wierzbicka, Anna (1991) Cross-cultural Pragmatics. The Semantics of Human Interaction. Berlin, New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
  • Yule, George (1996) Pragmatics (Oxford Introductions to Language Study). Oxford University Press.
  • Silverstein, Michael. 1976. "Shifters, Linguistic Categories, and Cultural Description", in Meaning and Anthropology, Basso and Selby, eds. New York: Harper & Row
  • Wardhaugh, Ronald. (2006). "An Introduction to Sociolinguistics". Blackwell.
  • Duranti, Alessandro. (1997). "Linguistic Anthropology". Cambridge University Press.
  • Carbaugh, Donal. (1990). "Cultural Communication and Intercultural Contact." LEA.
[edit]
睡眠质量差吃什么药 什么是支原体感染 遁形是什么意思 二甲双胍缓释片什么时候吃 为什么会一直拉肚子
梦见偷玉米是什么意思 来月经不能吃什么水果 得艾滋病有什么症状 主动脉硬化是什么意思 夏天为什么会感冒
血压什么时候最高 红斑狼疮是什么症状 喉痹是什么意思 焦虑失眠吃什么药最好 卵巢是什么
瘦肚子吃什么水果 属蛇的本命佛是什么佛 bbs是什么意思 优越感是什么意思 南京市长是什么级别
什么是双向抑郁hcv8jop1ns8r.cn cbd什么意思hcv8jop5ns8r.cn single是什么意思zhiyanzhang.com 什么爱hcv7jop7ns4r.cn 真菌镜检阴性是什么意思hcv8jop7ns3r.cn
总胆固醇高吃什么药好hcv9jop2ns2r.cn 间断是什么意思hcv9jop1ns3r.cn 2023年属兔的是什么命hcv7jop6ns1r.cn 叶酸什么时候吃合适adwl56.com 梦到抓了好多鱼是什么意思hcv9jop3ns4r.cn
肚子疼拉肚子挂什么科hcv9jop8ns3r.cn gcp是什么意思hcv9jop8ns2r.cn 什么叫精神病hcv9jop1ns5r.cn 拉肚子吃什么最好dajiketang.com 蒲公英有什么功效travellingsim.com
姜虫咬人有什么症状hcv8jop8ns8r.cn 胃疼能吃什么水果bjcbxg.com 盆腔检查做什么检查hcv8jop5ns5r.cn 扬州有什么特产dajiketang.com 是什么品牌hcv9jop4ns5r.cn
百度